The United States Supreme Court announced
its decision in Dobbs v. Jackson Women's Health Organization on June 24, 2022. The
ruling overturned the court’s decision nearly 50 years prior in Roe v. Wade
that women in the U.S. had a constitutional right to abortion, and several
states immediately introduced legislation to ban abortions from conception on. Occurring
as it did only a few months before the 2022 midterm elections, Dobbs featured
heavily in political discourse. Some Democratic party ads described a ban on
abortions even in cases of rape and incest as “cruel.”
Legislation that bans abortions from
conception onward is reminiscent of the Roman Catholic position on abortion as
a moral matter, and so it could be useful to consider the possible rationale of
such a ban by considering the Catholic position. It might also be useful to
consider why opponents of such a ban find it cruel to not allow exceptions for pregnancies
that result from rape and incest.
It is my hope that this article will help each
side understand the point of view of the other, see where they agree and where
they disagree, and facilitate respectful mutual engagement. I will sometimes
employ unrealistic hypothetical cases: investigating the moral judgments we make
about such cases can help us uncover what factors underlie our moral judgments
in real life cases.
In Section 1, I examine the moral doctrine
that underlies one approach to banning abortion yet permits other acts that
would also result in the death of a fetus (even when it is considered to have the
moral status of a person, a status that confers “maximum rights” on an entity).
In Section 2 I consider criticisms of the doctrine based on some of its problematic
implications. Then, in Section 3, I argue that based on the acts it seems to permit, the doctrine in fact provides a ground for the
permissibility of abortions. In Section 4 I consider whether there are
limits on applying this argument, and in Section 5 I consider whether and why
not permitting exceptions to abortion bans (for rape and incest) is cruel and
whether cruelty is a ground for opposition to such bans.
1. The Doctrine of Double Effect and the
morality of abortion
The ban on abortion in Catholic moral
theology can be largely explained by one part of a principle that is known as
the Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE). It claims that killing someone else (or intentionally
refraining from action in order to let them die), whether as an end in itself
or even as a means to achieve a greater good, is strictly prohibited. The DDE is
a general philosophical view not explicitly tied to Catholicism and is well
known for its role in traditional just war theory, which condemns intentionally
killing civilians as a means to win a war. The doctrine supports a ban on
abortion only if the conceptus at all stages of development, including the
embryo and fetus,[i]
is considered to have the moral status of a person.[ii] It
would not support a ban on, for example, intentionally killing a bird if (in a
hypothetical case) it were lodged in a woman’s womb. This suggests that
abortion bans attribute the moral status of persons to the fetus from
conception.
The prohibition in Catholic moral theology on
intentionally killing or letting die has been interpreted to imply that even if
both the woman and the fetus would die unless an abortion is performed, one may
not intentionally kill the fetus to save the woman. One must let them both die
because foreseeing their deaths, even with certainty, is not the same as
intending their deaths and intending death would make an act or omission
morally wrong on this view.
It may be difficult to see the difference
between foreseeing something (even with certainty) and intending it. Philosophers
use what is known as the Counterfactual Test to distinguish between these
concepts (even if imperfectly): Suppose that contrary to fact, some deadly effect
of your act (including omission to act) would not occur holding others
things constant. Would this provide a reason not to do your act? If not, then you
didn’t intend the effect. If the fact that the effect would no longer occur would
provide a reason not to do your act, then you intend the effect itself. For
example, consider a case where an abortion would save a woman’s life. An effect
of the procedure is that her fetus will die. Is the death of the fetus intended
or merely foreseen? Apply the Counterfactual Test, imagining that the fetus
would not die as a result of the abortion and could be raised to viability
outside the woman’s body. Knowing that the fetus would not die, would the woman
still pursue the abortion? If she would not, then she intends the death of the
fetus. If the fetus not dying would not give her a reason to refrain from the
abortion, the fetal death is a mere side effect.[iii]
Now let us consider another part of the DDE
which is based on the conceptual distinction between intentionally killing and
killing with mere foresight to a death. According to this second part, if one
acts with the intention to produce a greater good and someone dies as a side
effect, that death need not make the act morally impermissible. Yet the very
same death would make an act impermissible if it were brought about
intentionally as an end in itself or even as a means to a greater good. On this
ground, Catholic moral theology permits the removal of a pregnant woman’s cancerous
uterus though it is foreseen that doing this will result in the fetus’ death, even
if the fetus would be born alive before the woman dies of cancer were the uterus
not removed. (Similarly, in war causing foreseen collateral deaths of civilians
can sometimes be permissible when intentional deaths are not. This can include
bombing military sites when it is foreseen but not intended that some of the
bombs will also hit people nearby, killing them.) One view of the cancerous uterus
case is that removing the uterus kills the fetus as a side effect. Another
construal is that, since there is no attack (even unintended) on the fetus, removing
the uterus ends life support the woman is providing and so lets the fetus die (rather
than killing it) as an unintended foreseen side effect. Actively terminating
life support one is providing is typically thought, as a conceptual matter, to
be a letting die (whether or not it is permissible) rather than a killing. Just
as killing may involve either a foreseen or intended death, so letting die may
involve either a foreseen or intended death.[iv]
Some revisionists have attempted to
construe the death of the fetus in some abortions as an unintended side effect
and so possibly consistent with the DDE. For example, in a craniotomy crushing
the fetus’ skull involves an intended attack on the fetus, but the fact that it
consequently dies is said to be only a side effect of a necessary means to its
removal perhaps for the further end of saving the pregnant woman’s life. One could
use the Counterfactual Test to try to show this: There would still be a reason to
crush the skull to remove the fetus if, counterfactually, the fetus survived after
removal from the woman’s womb. Because this understanding of a craniotomy seems
implausible, another approach has been to revise the DDE so that it also rules
out intending the involvement of the fetus (as in crushing its skull) in a way
that foreseeably results in its death. Some philosophers make more fundamental
criticisms of the DDE, denying that intention determines an act’s permissibility
and offering other grounds to account for the impermissibility of many of the
acts that the DDE condemns.[v] In
this article, I will just focus on the DDE as traditionally understood.
State bans on abortion may depart in some
ways from the uses of the DDE we have considered. For example, we have looked
at the Catholic view of what the DDE implies about abortions involving a fetus
that would otherwise die. However, notably, some abortion bans in public
policy—departing from the Catholic view—do allow intentional killing of the
fetus in this circumstance. But what about cases in which it is not certain
that the fetus would otherwise die, and yet the pregnant woman’s life is at
stake? It is not clear whether the state laws that would ban all abortions
would permit, for example, the removal of a pregnant woman’s cancerous uterus
on the grounds that the death of a fetus that might survive were the cancer to
remain untreated is only foreseen and not intended. Insofar as state laws,
unlike the Catholic view, permit abortions to save the pregnant woman from a
threat to her life caused by the pregnancy, they presumably would also permit
removal of the cancerous uterus.
2. Problematic implications of the DDE
So far we have considered the DDE in
conjunction with the view that the fetus has the status of a person. We’ve seen
how the principle can be used as a defense for prohibiting abortion and at the
same time, how it can permit other procedures that also result in the death of
a fetus. Now let’s take a closer look at how it may be difficult to draw
conclusions about the morality of abortion based on the DDE.
The DDE permits killing as a side effect only
if one’s act will produce a good that outweighs that bad effect. Hence, if it were
permissible to remove the cancerous uterus and in doing so kill the fetus (that
would otherwise survive to viability) as a side effect, this would be because
saving the woman is seen as a greater good and the death of the fetus a lesser bad.
However, if both the woman and the fetus have the status of persons, and if in
leaving the cancer untreated the woman would die while the fetus would survive,
it is not clear why this should be so. To see this, imagine that the removal of
a woman’s cancerous uterus (hypothetically) had the unintended side effect of
killing a person outside her womb who was in no way dependent on her.[vi] The
DDE would not permit the removal of the uterus that causes the death given that
the woman’s living is not a greater good than the other person’s living. Furthermore,
if there were twin fetuses who had the status of persons in the woman’s
cancerous uterus, the greater good would seem to be the survival of two people rather
than one person.
Suppose the removal of the cancerous uterus
would nevertheless be permitted even when it causes two fetal side effect deaths.
This might be because the fetuses do not have the moral status of persons, or because,
unlike the person wholly external to the woman, the fetuses are imposing on her
and they stand to lose life that they only have due to this imposition. The
permissibility of removing the uterus in this case might also be because the
deaths, while a foreseen side effect of the procedure, would be a letting die
rather than a killing since there is no direct attack (intended, as in the case
of the craniotomy, or merely foreseen) on the fetus. After all, it would be implausible
if the DDE permitted a letting die with foreseen death only if a greater good
results. If that were the case, I couldn’t permissibly let someone die rather
than sacrifice my arm to save them since retaining my arm wouldn’t be a greater
good than that person surviving. But while it could be an admirable act beyond
the call of duty (known as supererogatory) to do so, I have no such moral
obligation.
Any or all of these factors could morally
distinguish a fetus (that dies when the uterus sustaining it is removed from
the woman’s body) from an external person (unconnected to the woman’s body yet who
would be killed as a result of her uterine removal) and could make removal of
the uterus permissible in one case and not the other.
Some of these factors may also open the
door to permissible abortions. For example, traditional Catholic moral theology
permits lethal self-defense against an aggressor so long as one does not intend
his death as an end or means (as when one pushes an aggressor away merely
foreseeing he will fall over a cliff and die). Although the fetus is not a
willing aggressor, it might be seen as what is called a “morally innocent
threat” because through no fault of its own it presents an imposition on the
woman’s body or additional threats to her well-being. This is in contrast to a
person outside her womb. The threatened woman might therefore, by this
reasoning, be entitled to defend herself (or seek another’s help to defend her)
against the threat—whether the threat is a cancerous uterus (where nullifying
the threat results in a fetal death as a side effect) or the fetus itself against
which one may need to act. Further, it is an implausible implication of the DDE
that one may not intentionally kill a willing aggressor if that is necessary to
protect oneself or others. Hence, it may even be permissible to intentionally
kill a morally innocent threat, especially if the life it loses is one it only
has due to imposing on the person who intends the killing to end the imposition.
I’ll discuss how this can be so further in Section 3.
3. How the DDE might bear on the
permissibility of abortions
In Section 2 we considered the possibility
that some factors (such as stopping an aggressive threat) may sometimes make
even intentional killing morally permissible. Now we’ll consider in more detail
whether intentionally killing a morally innocent fetus in an abortion could be
permissible.
That the DDE permits removing a pregnant
woman’s cancerous uterus is of significance in this regard. It shows that
abortion bans that use DDE reasoning and consider the fetus to have the moral
status of a person do not rely on two other distinct views: (i) a pregnant
woman has a duty to provide the use of her body to the fetus at great cost to
herself or on the flip side, (ii) a fetus has a right to use the woman’s body when it
needs it. If it did have such a right, the woman would not be permitted to have
her cancerous uterus removed when doing so leads to the death of a fetus that
would otherwise survive. Imagine that a woman’s fetus were initially growing
outside her body and would die if not transferred to her body. A ban on
abortion based on the DDE does not imply that the woman has a duty to transfer
it rather than let it die. And while the cancerous uterus case does not imply
that the woman may refuse to let the fetus use her body when the cost to her would
be much less than death, Catholic moral theology does not claim that the woman
has a duty to do so and it does not base an abortion ban on there being
such a duty.[vii]
Suppose actively terminating life-saving aid (e.g., one removes a person from a
breathing tube) is a case of letting die rather than killing. Then if abortion
involved only preventing or terminating assistance to a fetus to avoid the same
lesser costs to the woman, it might be permissible according to the DDE even if
it foreseeably leads to the fetus’ death.[viii]
In this respect, at least some supporters
of a ban on abortion agree (surprisingly) with some claims emphasized by Judith
Thomson in her groundbreaking 1971 article “A Defense of Abortion.” In that article, Thomson assumes only for the
sake of argument that the fetus is a person. She then argues that a person has
no right to use another’s body even to save their life. This is consistent with
the view that one does not have a duty to always bear a lesser loss to save
someone else from a greater loss (e.g., one is not morally obligated to give up
one’s arm to save someone’s life). Thomson thinks this implies that one may
detach another person if they are already using one’s body even when one’s life
or health is not at stake and when doing so will foreseeably lead to this other
person’s death. She sees such detachment as a permissible killing. We have
already seen that detachment may be an active form of letting die rather than a
killing; it involves neither a deliberate attack on the fetus nor an intention
to kill it as a means of removal. It is only in a follow-up article, “Rights
and Deaths,” that Thomson explicitly says that she means to justify intentionally
killing even an innocent person by either the woman or someone who chooses to
help her if this is necessary to stop the person’s use of the woman’s body
against her will.[ix]
By contrast, as we have already seen, some
argue for a ban on abortion because in their view it involves intentionally
killing a fetus as a means to remove it from a woman’s body. This is so even
while agreeing that she doesn’t have a duty in general to provide such support
to save the life of someone outside her body. The question is whether these two
positions are in tension with each other. In what follows, I aim to show that it
is possible to make the grounds for the permissibility of intentionally killing
the fetus in an abortion more precise if bans are not based on women having a
duty to sacrifice themselves for the fetus or the fetus having rights to use
her body to save its life per se.
Suppose the woman has no duty to provide
the fetus with use of her womb merely to save its life. Then when she is
pregnant she is providing life support to the fetus to which it has no right
even to save its life. This means that any right the fetus has to continue receiving
life support would have to be based on the possibility that intentionally killing
it to remove it is impermissible (since not being killed is not the same as having
one’s life actively saved).[x]
But (i) it is a mistake of the DDE to imply that it is never permissible to
intentionally kill (as discussed earlier), and (ii) since in being killed the
fetus would lose only life it is getting from imposition on the woman to which
it has no right merely to get that life, intentionally killing it (which
deprives it of that life) in order to end that imposition can be permissible.
This argument (which I first presented in my Creation and Abortion[xi])
does not merely point to the fact that the fetus is imposing on the woman’s
body in a way that she need not permit even to save someone’s life as this
could be true even when the imposition is not in fact saving someone’s life.[xii]
It emphasizes that she is in fact providing it with life support and so killing
the fetus deprives it of no more than the benefit of an imposition that is not
justified by the benefit it produces.
Suppose this argument for the
permissibility of intentionally killing the fetus (even if it is a person) in
order to stop providing it with some types of life-saving aid is correct. Killing
in order to stop all supererogatory aid (i.e., aid we don’t have a duty to
provide), even when it is saving life, might still be impermissible. For
example, suppose one needn’t give someone a large sum of money to save their
life. It is still impermissible to deliberately kill the person whose life is
being saved by the money even if that is the only way to get the money back.
Hence, it is the seriousness of imposition on someone’s body that also plays a
role in the justification of killing as a means to stop the bodily imposition
that provides life support.
4. Possible limits on this argument for permitting
abortion?
In Section 3, I offered an argument for the
permissibility of abortion even if the fetus is a person. Now I’ll consider whether
there might be limits to its applicability. Some argue that abortion can only
be permissible if the fetus is not a person. Thomson, by contrast, argues that
abortion is permissible even if the fetus is a person from conception onward
(although her own view is that the fetus becomes a person at a late stage of
pregnancy). It might be thought that if abortion is permissible when the fetus
does not have the status of a person and it is permissible even if it is always
a person, then abortion is permissible whether or not the fetus is a person.
However, this might not be true in virtue of the following issue that Thomson
does not discuss: If a fetus is not a person from conception onward and only
achieves personhood at a certain latter point of development, there may be a
moral difference between aborting it before versus after it reaches that point.
Presumably it is a less serious moral matter to kill a nonperson than a person.
If one is morally responsible for failing to do the less serious act within a
certain time frame and for then putting oneself in the position of having to do
the more serious act of killing a person, is it still permissible to abort a
person or should there be a time limit on abortion?[xiii]
This ground for a time limit does not depend on the moral significance of a
fetus’ stage of development per se. This is because if the fetus were a person
from conception onwards, there would have been no time at which one could have
aborted a nonperson, so killing a person in an abortion would still be
permitted.[xiv]
This ground for a time limit depends on whether or not abortion at an earlier, nonperson
stage is possible.
One possible response to this concern is to
consider whether a time limit would similarly apply to letting a fetus die
(rather than killing it). That is, suppose a woman had to take a harmless pill
every month to keep a pregnancy going. If she was able to stop taking the pill
early on before the fetus was a person but didn’t, is it permissible for her to
stop taking the pill when the fetus is a person? Suppose it’s permissible to
omit taking the pill even though taking it is so easy that doing so in order to
save a person would ordinarily be her moral duty (since in general the easier
it is to do an act that saves a person the more likely one has a duty to
perform it). Omitting it could be permissible because the fetus still has no
right to the use of her body despite her not having withdrawn aid earlier. This
would imply that in the case of delayed abortion in which the fetus has become
a person, it still would have no right to the use of the woman’s body to save
its life. This would make its abortion permissible since in being killed it would
only lose life it gets from use of her body to which it has no right for
purposes of retaining its life, and killing the fetus is the only way to stop
such use (as argued in Section 3).[xv]
5. What constitutes cruelty in abortion
bans, and can that be ground for opposing them?
Now let us consider why some think it is especially
cruel not to have a rape exception to a ban on abortion.[xvi] The
impression given by the ads in which this claim was made is that the cruelty is
a reason why a complete ban is wrong. In what follows, I will use hypothetical
cases to help tease apart factors that are typically combined in discussion of
pregnancies that result from rape. This will enable us to see which factors (alone
or in some combination) might be sufficient or necessary to ground an exception
to an abortion ban and how cruelty bears on this.
(A) The question of the woman’s moral
responsibility for her pregnancy, and thus for the fetus, is different for
victims of rape than for participants in consensual sex. A rape victim does not
bear any moral responsibility for her pregnancy since (i) she did not consent
to the sexual act, and (ii) she is not required to use contraception merely
because it is possible that she could be raped. We could imagine cases besides
rape in which the pregnant woman would not be morally responsible for the
presence of the fetus. For example, suppose a woman with a cognitive disability
consents to sex without realizing that she could become pregnant as a result.[xvii]
Then if the absence of responsibility for pregnancy grounded the rape
exception, abortion might also be permissible in this case. However, that
someone is not responsible for being in a situation that is bad for them (such
as unwanted pregnancy) does not yet show that there is a permissible way of
getting them out of that situation (nor that abortion is such a way).
Emphasizing the nonresponsibility ground
for the rape exception might suggest that engaging in voluntary sex (even with
contraception), which gives a woman at least partial responsibility for her
pregnancy, makes it harder to justify having an abortion. If this were so, it
would probably imply that responsibility also gives her a duty to provide the
fetus with the use of her womb independently of having a duty not to kill it to
remove it. Unlike the ground for the ban on abortion we have already
considered, this view about the role of moral responsibility for pregnancy connects
(i) a duty not to intentionally kill the fetus to remove it from the womb with (ii)
a duty to provide costly aid to the fetus rather than let it die. Thus it might
imply, where the DDE does not, that it is wrong to abort a fetus when doing so
would involve its merely foreseen death.[xviii]
That a ban based on the DDE does not permit a rape exception—because an
abortion in those circumstances would still intentionally kill a fetus as a
means—itself suggests that a ban based on the DDE need not be connected with judging
the morality of women’s sexual activity.
(B) One thing that focusing on
nonresponsibility for pregnancy omits is the use of force against a woman in
rape. It also omits that another person is acting on her body against her will or
without her consent which could occur even without force (e.g., when she is
drugged so as to be unable to resist sex). All these factors could also be
present in a case of nonvoluntary artificial insemination; the absence of
sexual intercourse would not reduce the strength of the ground (if there is
any) for an exception. All these cases involve wrongful involvement by another
person in addition to the woman’s pure nonresponsibility for the pregnancy. This
means that the woman who is raped is the victim of wrongdoing and has been
wronged (which is not true of the woman with the cognitive disability who
becomes pregnant in our earlier example).[xix] The
consequences of being wronged should be corrected when it is possible and
permissible to do so. However, that abortion would correct the consequences of being
wronged is not enough to show that it is a permissible means of doing so.
(C) When the rape exception is raised, some
refer to how horrible it is to be required to bear the biological offspring of
one’s rapist. (The emphasis is placed on “bearing” it, being complicit in its
development, rather than the fact of such an offspring existing.) This concern would
be void if the rapist used the semen of an innocent party to impregnate the
woman, yet doing so would not undermine the case for a rape exception. The
fetus would still be developing in her body due to the rapist’s act. Hence, bearing
the rapist’s offspring would not be a necessary condition for a rape exception
to the ban.[xx]
Opposition to the rape exception even to
eliminate carrying the rapist’s offspring might again be based on the DDE claim
that it is always morally wrong to intentionally kill a person, especially one
that is morally innocent (assuming the fetus has the moral status of a person),
even to correct the wrong that was done to another morally innocent person (the
woman impregnated by her rapist).
Even if this view is incorrect, another hypothetical
example can help make clear that ending pregnancy due to rape is not always
sufficient to justify killing. Suppose that removing a fetus produced by rape from
the woman’s womb would (somehow) require intentionally killing a second fetus
of that rape that is outside of and not dependent on the woman’s body. If fetuses
had the status of persons, it would be clearly wrong to kill the outside nondependent
fetus—and it would be wrong to characterize the choice not to kill it as
being cruel to the pregnant woman, even if by refraining from killing it we
denied the rape victim her only chance to have the other, dependent fetus removed
from her body. This is so despite the nonresponsibility of the pregnant woman,
the attack on her, her having to bear a rapist’s fetus, and that the fetus to
be killed would also be the rapist’s. If it made no difference to the
permissibility of killing the fetus in an ordinary abortion that it is imposing
and dependent for life on the woman’s body, then the impermissibility of
killing the outside nondependent fetus resulting from rape would undermine the
rape exception to the ban on abortion.
This case in which aborting the dependent
fetus involves killing the nondependent fetus shows that we must demonstrate
the permissibility of intentional killing before we can argue that it is cruel
to refuse to so kill. (If an act is impermissible, refusal to perform it can’t
be cruel.) It also suggests that we need to draw a distinction between (i) a
state of affairs being cruel and (ii) it being cruel not to stop that states of
affairs. For example, the U.S. Constitution does not permit “cruel and unusual
punishments.” Suppose that someone being tortured by a mechanical device is a
cruel punishment (and so constitutes a cruel state of affairs) but the only way
to stop this happening is to kill several innocent people. That the punishment
is cruel does not show that it is cruel not to stop it by the only means
available. Similarly, it might be a cruel fate to be carrying the offspring of
one’s rapist, but that’s not sufficient to show that refusal to terminate the
pregnancy is cruel. It is only after abortion has been found permissible that refusal
to permit it could be considered cruel. However, suppose one argues that abortion
is permissible on the ground that the fetus is imposing on the woman, would lose
only the benefit of that imposition, and
being killed is the only way to end that imposition. Then adding to that
argument that having to bear the offspring of rape is a cruel state of affairs can
help show that the imposition is significant enough to justify killing to end
it.
After providing such an argument for
permissibility, the cruelty of not allowing an abortion comes to the fore. Denying
permission for an impermissible act is not cruel but denying permission for a
permissible act can be. Hence, once it has been shown that abortion in a
particular case is permissible, the decision not to allow the abortion (which
would end what may be a cruel state of affairs) can be characterized as cruel.
The cruelty of the state of affairs is not sufficient alone to ground the
permissibility of abortion, but those who claim it is cruel not to permit
abortion in rape cases could be correct even if they are incorrect in claiming
that it being cruel not to permit abortions is an argument for the
permissibility of abortion when in fact it only follows from already
established permissibility.
Conclusion
In discussing points of agreement between
some opponents and proponents of the moral permissibility of abortion (e.g.,
about whether a woman has a duty to share her body in order to save a fetus) and
also arguing that contrary to the DDE intentional killing is sometimes
permissible, I introduced potential grounds for defending a woman’s right to seek
an abortion. I also argued that the truth of claims about the cruelty of
denying abortions (even to end cruel states of affairs) depends on first
showing that those abortions are permissible. This is by contrast to the permissibility
of abortions depending on the cruelty of not permitting them. If what I have
said is correct, banning abortion is not a morally justified policy and so can
be cruel even if the fetus is taken to have the moral status of a person.[xxi]
[i] Henceforth, I shall use “fetus” to refer to all stages of the
product of conception.
[ii] I leave it open that something other than an actual person could
have the moral status of a person.
[iii] Here is a further
example from war: Suppose (contrary to fact) that if one bombed a munitions
facility no civilians would be killed. Would this give one a reason not to
bomb? If not (is said), their deaths are shown to be mere foreseen side effects
whose absence would not interfere with the purpose of one’s bombing mission.
But if their deaths were required as a means to terrorize the population, one
would have a reason to call off one’s mission showing that in the actual
bombing case one intended their deaths.
[v] For example, J.J.Thomson in “Physician Assisted Suicide: Two Moral
Arguments,” 1999 Ethics 109 (3):497-518; “T.M. Scanlon in Moral
Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2010), and F.M. Kamm, “Terrorism and Intending Evil,” Philosophy
& Public Affairs, Vol. 36, No. 2 (Spring 2008), 157-186.
[vi] Being outside her body should be distinguished from imposing on and
being dependent on her. This is because we could imagine a hypothetical form of
pregnancy in which the fetus imposed on and was dependent on the woman by
growing around rather than in her.
[vii] However, according to the DDE, it would be morally impermissible to
let the fetus die because she intended its death rather than merely foreseeing
its death as an unintended side effect.
[viii] On Dec. 23 2022 an announcement was made that the contraceptive pill
Plan B prevents ovulation and does not prevent a fertilized egg (a zygote) from
implanting in the uterus (a process which some referred to as an abortion).
Suppose a pill did prevent a fertilized egg from implanting in the uterus by,
for example, blocking the route of the zygote to the uterus or making it
inhospitable to the zygote. This Revised Plan B would be comparable to blocking
the route to the uterus of the fetus growing externally without any attack on
the fetus. If the latter were permissible according to the DDE, it is not clear
why Revised Plan B should not be permissible as well according to the DDE.
[ix] See J.J. Thomson, “A Defense of Abortion,” Philosophy
& Public Affairs 1(1), 1971:47-66 and “Rights and Deaths,” Philosophy
& Public Affairs 2(2), 1973:146-159 which was her response to John
Finnis, “The Rights and Wrongs of Abortion: A Reply to Judith Thomson” Philosophy
& Public Affairs, 2 (2), 1973: 117-145. Many may fail to see the need
to complete the argument given in her first paper so as to justify a deliberate
attack on the fetus in abortion. Different ways of removing the fetus are
discussed in my Creation and Abortion
(N.Y.: Oxford University Press, 1992).
[x] One does not save someone’s life merely because one doesn’t kill
them.
[xi] For more on this particular argument which focuses on the fetus
losing only the benefit of an imposition to which it has no right merely to
save its life see Creation and Abortion.
[xii] Thomson’s cases often involve someone receiving life support.
However, her argument speaks of ending
use of one’s body that one needn’t provide even to save a life. This leaves it
open that one might end use of one’s body when it wasn’t actually saving
someone’s life. She does note that when someone is receiving life support from
using someone else’s body if one may not remove them, then they will wind up
getting support it was agreed they had no right to have merely to save their
life. But this is not sufficient to show that they may not have a right to keep
the support as a way to avoid being killed rather than merely in order to save
their life. My argument aims to show why their losing only life they get from
support makes it unnecessary to avoid killing them.
[xiii] I raised this issue in “Creation and Abortion Short” in my Bioethical
Prescriptions (N.Y.: Oxford University Press, 2013).
[xiv] By contrast the decision in Roe v. Wade placed emphasis on stages
per se in altering requirements for permissible abortions in different
trimesters.
[xv] There being other ways of removing the fetus that do not involve
killing it and do not require considerably more imposition on the woman than an
abortion could also limit the argument for abortion. For example, if the means
of removing the fetus to an external gestation device imposed on her no more
than removing it in an abortion, the former means may be required if the fetus
has the status of a person. I first discussed how real and hypothetical
external gestation devices could affect the right to seek an abortion in Creation
and Abortion.
[xvi] Cruelty is here not being considered as a person’s motivation but
rather as a characterization of an act, a refusal to act, or even a state of
affairs independent of motivation (as we shall see). Incest may usually involve
rape but its involving abuse by a parent or sibling may be thought to make it
worse. I will consider it a variation on rape.
[xvii] Science fiction type cases could also provide examples of
nonresponsibility. For example, suppose a woman unavoidably became pregnant by
cloning when she menstruates and this was either (a) an inexplicable unusual
occurrence or (b) a part of women’s natural biology that sometimes happens.
[xviii] For detailed consideration of how various forms of responsibility (including
intentional pregnancy) might or might not affect the permissibility of abortion
see Creation and Abortion.
[xix] Notice that she would also be a victim of a wrong if (in especially odd hypothetical cases)
impermissibly twisting her arm or cheating her out of money made her pregnant
against her will. Presumably the worse the wrong that results in pregnancy, the
more important the correction of the wrong would be (other things equal).
[xx] Nevertheless, having her body nourish an entity that conjoins the
rapist’s sperm with her egg may be particularly repellent to the pregnant woman.
Would it be worse or better if the rapist had managed to clone his embryo and
inserted it into the unwilling woman so there would be no mixing in the embryo
of the woman’s and rapist’s genetic material?
[xxi] I thank Thomas Douglas and two anonymous reviewers for comments on
earlier versions of this article. I also thank Margaret Collins for help in
making the article more accessible.
Back to Letters & Forthcoming Articles List