1 Introduction
Assertion is weak: you can rationally assert p even when you arenât sure of p, donât know p, and have low rational credence in p. That, anyway, is the (rather unorthodox) contention of this paperâone that goes against prevailing philosophical orthodoxy.
Our arguments build on arguments of Hawthorne et al. 2016 (henceforth HRS), who influentially argued that belief is weak in the corresponding sense. If they are right, what are the broader ramifications? The most common conclusion is that belief plays a less important role in epistemology and philosophy of language than many have thought. Instead, itâs a stronger notion (full belief, certainty, etc.), not necessarily corresponding to the ordinary usage of âbelieveâ or âthinkâ, that plays a central philosophical role (e.g. Stalnaker 1984, 2006; Williamson 2000, fc.). Indeed, HRS themselves argue that, while belief is weak, assertion is strong: it requires more than mere belief.
But an alternative reaction is available: perhaps beliefâthe weak attitude that our ordinary usage of âthinkâ and âbelieveâ corresponds toâshould continue to play a central philosophical role, despite being weak. We argue for this conclusion with respect to assertion: assertion is closely tied to belief, but both are weak.
Our claim that assertion is weak goes against a large literature that argues that assertion is strong, requiring knowledge or justified (strong) belief.1 Despite many disagreements, thereâs a near consensus in this literature that assertion is strong, in the sense that most, and perhaps all, of the following are false:
(i) you sometimes may assert p when your rational credence in p is less than 1;
(ii) you sometimes may assert p when you donât know p;
(iii) you sometimes may assert p when you arenât rationally sure of p;
(iv) you sometimes may assert p when your rational credence in p is much less than 1;
(v) you sometimes may assert p when your rational credence in p is less than 0.5.
We think all of these claims are trueâthat is what we mean when we say that assertion is weak. But weâll be happy if we only convince you that some of them are, for weâll still have succeeded in convincing you that assertion is much weaker than many have thought.
Our plan is to argue that assertion is weak (§§2â3) and then respond to the two most influential arguments that assertion is strongânamely, that itâs often natural to follow up an assertion with âHow do you know?â (§4), and that Moorean sentences like âItâs raining but I donât know itâ are always infelicitous (§5). Weâll conclude by sketching a positive theory of assertion, on which you should assert what you (weakly!) believe about the question under discussion.
2 The Weakness of Belief
We start by summarizing the case for the weakness of belief from Hawthorne et al. 2016, which weâll build on.2 When HRS say that belief is weak, they mean that âTim believes pâ or âTim thinks pâ can be true even if Tim is rational and has relatively little evidence for, and relatively low credence, in p.3 This is of course fully consistent with there being other, stronger doxastic states that philosophers, or ordinary speakers, can get at with terms like âoutright beliefâ or âfull beliefâ.4
The best way to motivate the weakness of belief is simply to look at examples. Start with a standard lottery case. Suppose thereâs a fair 2,000-ticket lottery in your workplace. Miriam buys one ticket. As has long been noted (Kyburg 1964; Levi 1967), it seems perfectly rational to think that Miriam will not win, even though your credence that Miriam will not win is less than 1.
The pattern generalizes. Suppose that John is coming for dinner and is bringing takeout. Liam knows he likes Indian best, then Chinese, then Thai, and finally Italian. More precisely, imagine that Liam thinks itâs 55% likely that John will get Indian, 25% likely heâll get Chinese, 15% likely heâll get Thai, and 5% likely heâll get Italian. If we ask Liam what he thinks John will bring, it seems fine for Liam to respond:
(1) I think heâll bring Indian.
Even more strikingly, it seems you can sometimes believe things that have probability less than 1/2. Suppose that in the lottery, 1,500 of your coworkers (Miriam, Mark, Marge,âŠ) bought one ticket each. Claire, meanwhile, bought the remaining 500 tickets. Although youâre by no means obligated to think Claire will win, if youâre asked, âWho do you think will win?â or âHow do you think the lottery will play out?â, itâs perfectly natural to reply:
(2) I think Claire will win.
In addition to such intuitions about cases, HRS also motivate the weakness of belief by noting that it generally sounds incoherent to assert that you have some doxastic inclination toward a claim but then deny belief in it:
(3) ?? Claire will probably win, but itâs not as if I think sheâll win.
(4) Claire will probably win, but itâs not as if I know sheâll win.
3 The Weakness of Assertion
HRS claim not just that belief is weak, but that belief is weaker than assertion, arguing against Entitlement Equality, which says, roughly, that belief and assertion have the same standards. More carefully, hereâs our understanding of Entitlement Equality (slightly altered from HRS, with the goal of having a clearer target). Let your epistemic situation include everything thatâs potentially relevant to what you are (epistemically) warranted in believing or asserting.6 Entitlement Equality says that an epistemic situation entitles you to believe p iff it entitles you to assert p.7
HRSâs central argument against Entitlement Equality comes from contrasts like these:
(5)
I think Miriam will lose, but I donât know sheâll lose.
#Miriam will lose, but I donât know sheâll lose.
(6)
I think Johnâll bring Indian, but Iâm not completely confident that he will.
#Johnâll bring Indian, but Iâm not completely confident that he will.
But hold that thought. Before rebutting the core arguments that assertion is strong (§§4â5), we will give three positive arguments that itâs weak.
3.1 Cases
Our first argument is simple: people make weak assertions all the time, without any apparent infelicity or irrationality. This is not to say that weak assertions canât be challengedâthey can beâbut, as we discuss in §3.1.2, that doesnât show theyâre irrational.
We will give a few cases that illustrate the point, and then explore some potential responses.
3.1.1 Argument
Start with Miriam. Recall that Miriam has one ticket in a fair 2,000-ticket lottery. Consider:
(7)
[Lucy:] Miriam, are you going to start saving for retirement this year?
[Miriam:] No. I entered the lottery instead.
[Lucy:] Thatâs nuts. Youâre not going to win the lottery!
Likewise, recall that Liam is 55% confident that John will bring Indian, 25% confident of Chinese, 15% confident of Thai, and 5% confident of Italian. Consider:
(8)
[Mark:] What will John bring for dinner?
[Liam:] Heâll bring Indian. Thatâs his favorite, after all.
Or recall Claire. Sheâs bought 500 of the 2,000 lottery tickets, while 1,500 coworkers each have one of the remaining tickets. Consider:
(9)
[Lucy:] Who do you think is going to win the lottery?
[Jill:] Itâll be Claire. She bought 500 tickets!
For another case, consider the 2021 Democratic primary in New York City. Thirteen nominees were on the ballot, and extrapolating outcomes from polls was complicated by the fact that the outcome was decided by ranked-choice voting, meaning it depended not just on votersâ preferred candidate but potentially on all of their conditional preferences. Plausibly, then, oneâs rational credence in any particular outcome should have been relatively low. Nonetheless, it seems that there would be nothing wrong, normatively speaking, with a conversation like this:
(10)
Eric Adams will win. Heâs the establishment choice.
No! It will be Maya Wiley. The progressives have coalesced around her.
I disagree. Wall Street will make sure Ray McGuire wins.
(11)
Whoâs gonna win the race this afternoon?
Slippery Peteâs gonna win this one.
(12)
How many people are coming to the party tomorrow?
17. (Thatâs how many people RSVPâd.)
(13)
What will the weather be next Tuesday?
Itâs going to rain.
Our examples so far have been future-directed. This is unsurprising: we think the standards of assertion vary with context (§6), and contexts where we are talking about the future are ones where itâs usually common ground that little certainty is to be had, and hence where the standards for assertion will naturally be taken to be relatively low. Nevertheless, in some contexts, past-directed weak assertions are also fine.9 For a simple example, consider a case above like the mayoral primary. After the votes are in but before they are counted, we can imagine the very same argument going on in the past tense. (âWho won?â âEric Adams, for sureâ âNo, Maya Wileyâ, etc.) Or consider:
(14)
[Child:] How did the dinosaurs go extinct?
[Parent:] A meteor 20 miles wide struck the Earth, and the debris heated up the atmosphere to hundreds of degrees!
(15) [Discussing the Great Seattle Fire of 1889:]
I wonder what it looked like.
Well obviously it was cloudy. (Itâs Seattle, after all.) So I bet the fire was eerily reflecting off the clouds.
If youâd like a recipe, variants on preface-paradox cases (Makinson 1965) can be used to generate natural cases of weak assertion. Suppose youâve gotten 98 âyesâ RSVPs to the Met Gala. Itâs a hot ticket, so for each âyesâ, your rational credence that that guest will come is very high (perhaps you even know theyâll come). Nevertheless, itâs unlikely that all of them will show up. (If each guest has a 1% chance of not showing up, and the chances are mutually independent, itâs only 37% likely that all 98 will come.) But still, the following exchange seems fine:
(16)
How many guests will be at the Met Gala this year?
Ninety-eight.
Now, some think that you can know in cases like these. Most significantly, HolguĂn (2021) argues that knowledge is often very weak, so that all of the asserted propositions above are in fact known. This of course runs counter to orthodoxy in epistemology (e.g., Williamson 2000). Still, if youâre convinced that knowledge can be weak, then you might agree that assertion is weak in senses (i) and (iii)â(v) above, but not in sense (ii): assertion still requires (weak!) knowledge.
If so, then you agree with us that assertion is much weaker than itâs standardly taken to be. Still, we think even this weak view of assertion is too strong: there are cases where you can assert p even when you manifestly donât know p even in a weak sense. For instance, suppose you are on a game show and youâre asked what year the Seven Yearsâ War started. You say:
(17) I donât know. I know it was in the 1700s, but I donât know more than that.
(18) Okay, well youâre out of lifelines, so youâll just have to guess.
(19) Ok, hm. The war started in 1760.
So our first argument is simply that weak assertions are perfectly acceptable in many contexts. No doubt some will be unconvinced; so before moving on to our next argument, weâd like to address a few reasons for skepticism.
3.1.2 Replies
To begin, you might think that while our judgments about these cases are right, these cases are simply not what philosophers have had in mind when they have talked about assertion. There are lots of other speech actsâpredictions, guesses, speculations, etc.âwhich can be weak, and the cases we have given here are instances of those speech acts (see Benton and van Elswyk 2020). But assertion proper is strong.
On the one hand, we have no objection to finer-grained taxonomies of speech acts, and we have no attachment to the word âassertionâ to describe the category of speech act we have been investigating; call them âsayingsâ if youâd prefer. But we think that by far the most natural way of drawing these finer-grained distinctions is normative. For instance, we might say that assertions are distinguished by being governed by such-and-such strong norms. But if this is simply stipulated as a taxonomical criterion, then this is no way of defending the claim that assertion is strong. If, on the other hand, this is being argued as a substantive claim, then some independent criterion must be given to distinguish assertions proper from the speech acts we have been considering so far. But we know of no such criterion.
Still, you might think that there is no reason to lump together all these speech actsâroughly, all communicative uses of declarative sentences. But we think they in fact constitute an interestingly unified class of speech acts. For even if we can draw finer-grained distinctions, there are two rather striking normative facts which bind together all communicative uses of declarative sentences. First, all speech acts across this class are subject to a kind of anti-Moorean constraint: conjoining any of them with expressions of uncertainty (âp, but I donât know pâ) leads to striking infelicity (see §5). Second, across this whole class, it is generally unacceptable to say something unless you think it is true (see §6).
In short: we have a clear object of study (communicative uses of declarative sentences), delineated in non-normative terms, which are subject to unified norms. Our project is figuring out what those norms are, and our central claim is that they are weak. This is consistent with other projects which fine-grain that class of speech acts; but unless that fine-graining is done non-normatively, that is no way at all of saving the claim that assertion is strong.
Another worry: you might accept that people say things like this all the time, but doubt the evidential value of that observationâperhaps theyâre just violating the norms? Taken too generally, this reply also undermines the methodology of the arguments for strong norms of assertion. Those arguments are built on patterns about what people say in everyday conversations. Either we take those patterns seriously, or we donât. If we do, then data like the above about the ordinariness of weak assertions must be taken seriously, too. If we donât, then we can dismiss this weak-assertion dataâbut, on pain of cherry-picking, we must also dismiss the data that support strong norms of assertion. We are not sure where that kind of methodological skepticism would land, vis-Ă -vis the norms of assertion, and we will not pursue that question. Rather, in line with the existing literature, weâll continue to take seriously how people speak, criticize each other, and respond to criticism, as evidence about what the norms of assertion are.
But, even if you agree with this methodological point, you might still think that in these particular cases, people simply are violating the norms of assertion. Aside from the general arguments for strong norms which we will discuss below, however, we can only see one reason for thinking this: namely, that pushback is possible in these cases. That is, we can almost invariably criticize weak assertions by raising counter-possibilities. For instance, when Lucy tells Miriam sheâs not going to win the lottery, Miriam can reply: âYou donât know that! My ticket is as good as anyone elseâs. I could certainly win.â
Does this show that Lucyâs assertion was unwarranted? No. Aside, perhaps, from mathematical or logical contexts, itâs always possible to raise counter-possibilities, as we know from the literature on skepticism (Lewis 1970, 1996; DeRose 1995). If Miriam says âMy car is parked around the blockâ, you can push back: âAre you absolutely certain? What if it was stolen? What if it was towed? What if youâre a brain in a vat being prodded by scientists?â Most think that the possibility of this kind of conversational move doesnât show that Miriam shouldnât have said what she said. So the felicity of pushback doesnât show that weak assertions are unwarranted.
Moreoverâas usualâpushback against the pushback is possible. In the lottery case, Lucy can say âNo, youâre not going to win, Miriam. You canât latch onto marginal possibilities like thatâ. In the car case, Miriam can say: âWell, thatâs very unlikely, so Iâm going to stick with my original claim: my car is parked around the block.â Patterns in pushback, and in pushback pushback, donât show an asymmetry between weak assertions and strong ones. Of course, the stronger your evidence for p, the more ammunition youâll have to push back against pushback. But that doesnât show that there is a categorical distinction.
3.2 Elicitation
Our second argument that assertion is weak is based on how we elicit assertions.
3.2.1 Argument
Our key observation is that asking someone what they think about some subject matter X is a standard way to elicit outright assertions about X.
For example, consider a primary election with five viable candidates. Marta is a close watcher of politics. She doesnât know what will happenâ no one does. Still, the following exchange is perfectly natural:
(20)
[Latif:] What do you think will happen in the race?
[Marta:] Joe will win.
Likewise, coming back to the case of John getting takeout: Liam doesnât know what John will do. Still, itâs perfectly fine to ask:
(21) What do you think John will bring for dinner?
(22) Heâll bring Indian.
By contrast, itâs actually somewhat weird to elicit assertions by asking someone what they are sure or certain of (Turri 2010b). This is especially pronounced in circumstances like the election, where itâs common ground that certainty is not to be had: âWhat are you certain of about the election?â is, of course, a coherent question, but itâs not the normal way to invite someone to make assertions about it, and will probably elicit completely uninteresting claimsâthat the election will take place, etc.âwhich fall far short of what someone might be prepared to say in response to the question of what they think about the election.
In sum: if the norm of assertion is strong, itâs puzzling why itâs so natural to elicit assertions with questions with the form âWhat do you think?â.
3.2.2 Replies
A natural response to this argument is to deny that the above responses to âWhat do you thinkâŠâ questions ((20b) and (22)) are asserting what they appear to assert. When you ask someone what they think about pâthe response goesâyouâre asking about their beliefs; so when they respond by saying p, they are not asserting p at all. Instead, what they are asserting is âI believe pâ, with âI believeâ simply elided (cf. Benton and van Elswyk 2020). So e.g., (20b) is not an assertion that Joe will win, but an assertion about Martaâs beliefs: âI think that Joe will winâ. If so, the above exchanges donât tell us anything at all about the strength of assertion.
In fact, you might be inclined to generalize this response: perhaps all our cases which appear to be weak assertions of p are really assertions of âI think that pâ or âProbably pâ, with the hedge simply unpronounced.
But this is wrong. We have two arguments against it. The first is that Moorean assertions are acceptable for overtly hedged assertions, but not otherwise. Compare:
(23)
[Latif:] Who do you think will win?
[Marta:] I think that Joe will win, but I donât know.
[Marta:] # Joe will win, but I donât know.
This is enough to vitiate this response, we think. For completeness, we have a second argument that ellipsis of the proposed kind simply is not possible. To see this, suppose that, instead of (20a), Marta is asked a third-personal belief question like (24):
(24) What does Mark think will happen in the race?
(25) ??Joe will win.
Ellipsis is possible in cases like this, but only with an overt complementizer. Hence, (26) is easily interpreted as an answer to (24), with the form âMark thinks that Joe will winâ, and it is not easily interpreted as an assertion about who will win:
(26) That Joe will win.
These contrasts suggest that elision of the proposed kind is not available for assertions without an overt complementizer. If this is right, it provides a second argument that the deflationary response we are considering is wrong: a claim like (20b) is an assertion about who will win, not about Martaâs beliefs after all.
A second potential reply notes that elicitation with âWhat do you think?â isnât always possible. In particular, when you think A knows about X, it is weird to ask what they think about X. If A saw what happened at the game, it is strange to ask A âWho do you think won?â But this is readily explained on standard theories of anti-presupposition: since âknowsâ is a presuppositional competitor of âthinksâ, âS thinks pâ leads to the inference that âS knows pâ is false (Percus 2006); and this inference projects out of questions, since presuppositions project out of questions. So âWhat do you think about X?â leads to the inference that the addressee doesnât know about X, and so it will be peculiar to ask what A thinks about X if it is common ground that A knows about X. (This also explains why âWhat do you thinkâ elicitations are more natural in future-directed contexts, where we often donât know. But, as we saw, it can also be used to elicit assertions about the past if you think the addressee doesnât know.)
3.3 Attitude Reports
Our final argument is based on what kinds of attitude reports are licensed by assertions.
3.3.1 Argument
First, when A asserts p, what are we inclined to conclude? The strong assertion story says that (ceteris paribusâassuming norms are satisfied) we can conclude that A is sure that p, or certain that p, or takes themselves to know p (depending on the strong norm theory). The weak assertion story says that we can only conclude that A thinks that p. And the prediction of the weak story is correct.
To see this, suppose that Ezra overhears this exchange:
(27) [Mark, on the phone with Liam:] What will John bring for dinner? [Listens.] Okay, thanks. [Hangs up.]
(28)
John will bring Indian.
Liam said that John will bring Indian.
Liam thinks that John will bring Indian.
(29)
Liam is certain that John will bring Indian.
Liam is sure that John will bring Indian.
Liam takes himself to know that John will bring Indian.
Another consideration is this. The most natural way for Ezra to ask Mark what Mark has found out is to say:
(30) [Ezra:] What does Liam think Johnâll bring?
(31)
[Ezra:] What does Liam know Johnâll bring?
[Ezra:] What is Liam sure Johnâll bring?
A final related point builds on the observations by HRS about the difficulty of interpreting sentences like (3), repeated here:
(3) ??Claire will probably win, but itâs not as if I think sheâll win.
(32)
??Claire will probably win, but Iâm not saying sheâll win.
Claire will probably win, but Iâm not sure sheâll win.
(33)
??I think Claire will win, but Iâm not saying sheâll win.
I think Claire will win, but I donât know sheâll win.
3.3.2 Replies
Weâll reply to three potential concerns.
First, on the last data point: a potential confound is that the bad variants in (32) and (33) are mixing attitude verbs with speech-act reports. But this does not in general lead to infelicity; witness:
(34)
I want Claire to win, but Iâm not saying she will.
I consider it possible that Claire will win, but Iâm not saying she will.
Second, in ordinary circumstances, you can infer from Liam saying âI think John will bring Indianâ that Liam doesnât know what John will bring, while you canât infer this about Ezra if he says outright âJohn will bring Indianâ. However, this has a straightforward explanation which is compatible with the weakness of assertion: as we discussed above, âI think pâ leads to an anti-presupposition that âI know pâ is false (and presumably also a scalar implicature that âIâm sure pâ is false as well, as Bach (2008) discusses). By contrast, p alone does not, since âI {am sureknow} pâ is not (on standard theories) an alternative to p alone (Katzir 2007). Thus Liamâs statement gives rise to the inference that he isnât sure and doesnât know that p, while Ezraâs statement doesnât. But this is all perfectly compatible with assertion being weak.
Third, in both the case of belief and assertion, these incoherent sequences can be improved by pulling âwillâ out of the contraction and focusing it: âClaire will probably win, but Iâm not saying she will winâ is at least improved. But this supports rather than undermines our point: if assertion were strong, focusing âsayâ should bring out exactly the contrast we aim to communicate here, just as in âClaire will probably win, but I donât know she willâ. The fact that we canât bring out these contrasts by focusing âsayâ, and need to focus âwillâ instead, supports our claim that âsayâ is not strong. Focusing âwillâ improves things by making salient the contrast between âprobablyâ and âwillâ: our point is not that asserting âClaire will probably winâ and âClaire will winâ amount to the same thing (they obviously donât), but rather that the gap between them canât be brought out simply by emphasizing âsayâ, while the corresponding gap with a strong predicate like âknowsâ can be brought out that way.
4 âHow Do You Know?â
This completes our positive argument that assertion is weak. Weâll now turn to rebutting the most prima facie compelling arguments that assertion is strong. Weâll start by addressing the argument from âHow do you know?â; then, in §5, weâll explore Moorean utterances.
A common argument for the knowledge norm is the fact that when someone makes an assertion, itâs usually fine to reply âHow do you know?â Since âHow p?â presupposes p, this suggests that the very act of asserting p communicates that you know p (Williamson 2000, 252â253).
But this conclusion is not true in general.13 While âHow do you know?â is often a natural response to assertions, it isnât always. Consider:
(36)
[Mark:] What will John bring?
[Liam:] I just donât know.
[Mark:] Well, fine, but what do you think?
[Liam:] Hm, ok, letâs see. Heâll get Indian. Thatâs his favorite, after all.
(37) How do you know heâll get Indian?
In fact, further reflection on the naturalness of various responses to assertions provides further evidence that assertion requires belief but not, in general, knowledge (or certainty). Compare the responses in (38):
(38) [Liam:] John will bring Indian.
Do you know that?
Are you sure?
??Do you think that?
By contrast, if thereâs no knowledge or certainty norm, but there is a belief norm, the contrast is easy to explain. (38c) feels aggressive or redundant, because the norms of assertion already require Liam to believe what he says;14 whereas (38a) and (38b) are perfectly reasonable attempts to ascertain more information about Liamâs mental state, since assertion doesnât require knowledge or certainty.15
Nevertheless, you might wonder: if assertion is weak, why is âHow do you knowâ such a natural follow-up in so many cases? Well, of course, it is perfectly consistent with the weakness of assertion that in many particular contexts, we do expect people to only say what they know, and the naturalness of âHow do you know?â in those contexts may well show just that (see §6 for more discussion). But that doesnât mean that assertion requires knowledge in general.
Two further points. The first is that, even insofar as assertion often goes with knowledge, the relevant sense may may be very weak (see, again, HolguĂn 2021). This plausibly is all thatâs expected when people causally ask âHow do you know?â, which in many contexts is, intuitively, just a request for you to state your reasons for belief (cf. McKinnon 2012). Again, though, let us emphasize that we donât think that assertion in general requires even this weak attitude, since there is nothing whatever wrong with denying knowledge tout court, and then going on to assert, as in (36).
Second, if the norms of assertion are weak in general, we will constantly be negotiating and exploring the strength of commitment that we expect or can assume in any particular context. Obviously sometimes you should only say what you know, or are sure of. When under oath, youâd be ill-advised to just say whatever you think! And plausibly, using presuppositional questions like âHow do you know?â is one effective way to negotiate the local standards (using a question like this shows that I expect that, in this context, we are only saying what we know, in at least some sense of âknowâ). In §6, weâll briefly sketch a theory which accounts for this flexibility.
Upshot: on reflection, judgments about follow-ups to assertions show that assertion is weak, not strong.
5 Moorean Sentences
We turn, finally, to what we see as the best argument for defenders of strong assertion: Moorean sentences. Recall the contrast in (5):
(5)
I think Miriam will lose, but I donât know sheâll lose.
#Miriam will lose, but I donât know sheâll lose.
5.1 Guessing Contexts
First observation: itâs sometimes the case that (1) you may assert âI donât know pâ (since you donât know p); (2) you may assert p (since assertion is weak); but (3) you still canât assert âp but I donât know pâ. In these cases, the SAS cannot explain what is wrong with such an assertion.
This comes out clearly in contexts where you are explicitly asked to guess. Recall the game show scenario, where you are asked what year the Seven Yearsâ War started. You donât know, and you can say as much: âAll I know is that it started in the 1700sâI really donât know more than thatâ. The host insists you guess, and you say:
(41) Ok, hm. The war started in 1760.
Alternately, suppose that, in the same context, the game show host, instead of asking you to take a guess, prompts you by asking, âDo you know whether the war started in 1760?â In response to that prompt, it seems like you canâyou shouldâsay:
(42) No, I donât know whether the war started in 1760.
But what you canât do is assert a Moorean conjunction which puts these two assertions together, as in (43a), or the subsequent variants:16
(43)
#The war started in 1760, but I donât know whether the war started in 1760.
#I have no idea when the war started, but the war started in 1760.
#The war started in 1760, but Iâm not sure that it started in 1760.
This is surprising. After all, itâs common ground that you donât know when the war started. Itâs completely fine to say that you donât know or that you arenât sure. Itâs also completely fine to say your guess. What you canât do, apparently, is combine these speech acts: you canât simultaneously say p while explicitly admitting that you are less than certain of p.
The SAS canât account for this. It says that whatâs wrong with Moore sentences is that you are flouting the norm of assertion. But it is clearly normatively fine to assert (41), even though itâs common ground that you donât know it. So whatâs wrong with asserting it, and also admitting that you donât know it? Even those who like strong assertionâand so think there is something normatively wrong with (41)âshould agree that thereâs a striking contrast between (41) and the Moorean variants in (43). The SAS canât account for this contrast. After all, it says that the same thing is wrong with both assertions. This shows that the SAS does not yield a general account of Moorean sentences.
There could be different explanations of these phenomena. Perhaps the SAS explains Moorean infelicity in cases of non-guessing assertions, and something else does so in guessing cases. But this seems unlikelyâ more plausible is that whatever explains the infelicity in guessing cases also explains it in the others. One story you might tell along these lines is that the infelicity of the assertions in (43) arises from the irrelevance of the Moorean conjunct. But, first of all, if relevance explained the badness of these Moorean cases, then there is no reason to think it wouldnât account for all Moorean phenomenaâin which case the SAS would be otiose, and we would still conclude that Moorean sentences provide no evidence for strong norms. But second, the relevance story is not plausible. For adding conjuncts about your mental state is generally fine, as long as those conjuncts donât express uncertainty:
(44)
The war started in 1760, and Iâm sure of that.
The war started in 1760, that I know.
The war started in 1760, I remember that from high school.
5.2 Certainty
Our second argument against the SAS is that it canât explain the infelicity of Moore sentences involving attitude verbs stronger than âknowâ, like the following:
(45)
#John will bring Indian, but Iâm not completely confident that he will.
#John will bring Indian, but thereâs the tiniest chance that he wonât.
#Miriam lost, but I wouldnât bet my life that she lost.
#Slippery Peteâs going to win this, but Iâm not absolutely certain he will.
#The butternut squash are in aisle 4, but I canât absolutely, infallibly rule out every possibility in which they arenât.
But these norms are, on the face of it, absurd. Weâre almost never in such strong epistemic positions about the things we ordinarily talk aboutâwhere the butternut squash is, whether Miriam will win the lottery, whether your car is still out back. Yet this ordinary fact of life does not stop us from speaking. If Liam tells you he left his car around the corner, and you respond by asking how he could possibly be willing to bet his life on this, you arenât demonstrating mastery of the norms of assertion.
The SAS thus faces a dilemma. On the one hand, it may simply not try to explain these Moorean infelicities. But then we need an alternate explanation; and again, that alternate explanation will presumably extend to the basic cases with âknowâ, making the SAS otiose. On the other hand, the SAS may try to explain theses casesâbut if it does so, it will have to say patently absurd things about the strength of assertion.
Others have pointed to this concern and responded in various ways.17 Williamson 2000 suggests that the infelicity stems from the fact that we resist allowing the contextual standards for knowledge to come apart from those for certainty. Relatedly, Stanley 2008, Clarke 2018, Dorst 2019, and Beddor 2020b suggest that these patterns support a certainty (or credence-one) norm of assertion, but suggest the relevant kind of âcertaintyâ is not overly demanding because itâs context-sensitive (cf. Moss 2019).
These replies donât seem very promising. First, itâs not at all clear how weâd extend this story to the full range of constructions we saw above. For instance, itâs not plausible that âIâd bet my life that pâ has any default, context-sensitive reading on which itâs entailed by âI know that pâ.
Second, it is fine to explicitly stand by p when you assert it but arenât maximally certain:
(46)
[Susanne:] My car is around the corner.
[Jacopo:] Are you absolutely, completely certain of that? Can you rule out with complete confidence any other possibility?
[Susanne:] No, of course not. Still, I stand by what I said.
(47)
[Lucy:] You wonât be able to afford this vacation, Miriam.
[Miriam:] You donât know that! After all, I might win the lottery.
[Lucy:] Of course, but donât be silly. You arenât going to win, and so you wonât be able to afford this vacation.
(48)
[Catherine:] John will bring Indian for dinner.
[Ezra:] So you think heâll bring Indian?
[Catherine:] ??No, of course not. But I still stand by what I said.
Third, if the norm of assertion is maximally strong, exchanges like
(49) should be fine:
(49) [Liam:] John will bring Indian
[Ezra:] ??Why are you willing to bet your life on that?
[Ezra:] ??What makes you absolutely certain of that?
Defenders of the SAS may, again, appeal to a form of contextualism in response. Suppose that whenever you ask someone about certainty (or whether they are willing to bet their life on something, or whatever), you raise the stakes for those things. If someone asserts p in context c1, they must be absolutely certain of p, relative to the certainty/sureness-standards of context c1. But simply asking them if they are certain of p moves you to a new context, c2, with higher certainty/sureness-standards, relative to which they might not be certain.
We think this is implausible. First, we donât know of any other kind of context-sensitive language where the contextual standards are invariably changed simply by using that language. This position would also make the norms of assertion strangely ineffable: youâre supposed to be (absolutely) certain of whatever you say, but relative to standards that we canât (in a stable way) talk about, since talking about them ipso facto raises the standards.
More pointedly, if the standards for âcertainâ can be changed so easily across assertions, itâs unclear why they canât also change within a single assertion in the same way. But clearly they canâtâif they could, then âp, but Iâm not absolutely certain of itâ would be fine, since âabsolutely certainâ would be interpreted relative to higher standards for certainty than the first conjunct.
Finally, there is direct evidence against the view that merely asking someone whether they are certain about something is enough to raise the stakes for certainty ascriptions. Consider:
(50)
[Catherine:] Iâm sure John will bring Indian for dinner.
[Ezra:] Oh, youâre certain that John will bring Indian?
[Catherine:] ??No, of course Iâm not certain.
In sum: if the SAS were to account for the full range of Moorean sentences, it would have to say that the norms of assertion are maximally strong. But that is patently implausible. Once again, the SAS falls short.
5.3 An Alternative
Our main goal in this section is negative: to argue that the SAS does not explain Moorean phenomena, and hence that Moorean phenomena do not show that norms of assertion are strong.
We want to briefly say something positive about what the explanation could be. This idea is separable from the rest of the picture we are pushing, and we are not sure itâs right; indeed, weâre confident more needs to be said. But we want to give some sense of how we might go about accounting for Moorean phenomena in a way consistent with the weakness of assertion.
Start with an observation from Silk 2015, 2022 and Mandelkern 2021: Moorean infelicities extend to commands. Thereâs something wrong with giving an order to do p while also asserting that p might not happen:
(51) #Close the door! I donât know if you will.
Mandelkern suggests that something similar might be applied to Moorean phenomena in general (attributing the suggestion to Daniel Rothschild).19 That is the idea weâd like to explore hereâthat there is a norm along the lines:Imperative Posturing: In performing the speech act of giving an order, act as if you are absolutely certain you will be obeyed.
This norm would account for the basic contrasts which motivate HRS to reject Entitlement Equality: while, per this norm, you canât ever assert a sentence like âp but Iâm not sure that pâ, itâs consistent with it to assert a sentence with the form âI think p but Iâm not sure that pâ, since such a sentence does not amount to an assertion of p. This norm also accounts for the various data points that the SAS misses. It applies equally to explicit guessing contexts as to any other context of assertion, which means that it will account for the infelicity of Moorean assertions in those contexts. And Epistemic Posturing says you must adopt a pretense of maximal certainty, which means that it will account for Moorean sentences with âcertainâ, âbet my lifeâ, and so on.Epistemic Posturing: In performing the speech act of asserting p, act as if you are absolutely certain of p.
Since Epistemic Posturing only applies within single speech acts, there is, according to it, no need to maintain a pretense of absolute certainty before or after an assertion. Moreover, since the norm requires a pretenseânot actual certaintyâit doesnât license the conclusion that the speaker is absolutely certain of what they said; all it licenses is the conclusion that the speaker was (in the moment of assertion) acting as if they were certain of p (more on this in a moment).20
And, of course, this approach is consistent with thinking that assertion is weak in general: according to this norm, itâs fine to assert p when you are less than certain of p, provided that (while making the speech act) you adopt a pretense of certainty.
To help bring out the considerations in favor of Epistemic Posturing, let us contrast it with a subtly different, broadly Stalnakerian approach discussed in Hawthorne et al. 2016, which we think is prima facie attractive but on reflection less appealing than Epistemic Posturing.21 This approach maintains that there is a strong norm of assertion, but that weâre often happy to simply pretend weâre satisfying it.
You might be inclined to think this is a way of saving a knowledge norm, and hence something like the SAS. But we arenât convinced that much gets saved, either (i) of the idea that there is a knowledge norm nor (ii) of the idea that there is a knowledge norm. First: for this reply to account for the certainty data above, weâd need the norm in question to be a norm of absolute certainty, not merely knowledge. That is, this view wonât account for Moore sentences with âIâm not certainâ, âI wouldnât bet my lifeâ, and so on unless the norm says to assert p only if you are absolutely certain that p. And, attractive as the knowledge norm has been to many, few have been inclined to defend a norm of absolute certainty.
But suppose we did take on board a certainty norm, and then say that it can be satisfied by pretense. That would be a strange kind of norm indeed. In general norms can be reasonably violated in various ways when they are outweighed by other considerations. But when a norm is reasonably violated, there is not in general a requirement that we pretend we are satisfying the normâwe might do so, but we certainly need not. So for this approach to work, it would have to say that there is a certainty norm of assertion, but itâs a special kind of norm: itâs a norm that we can reasonably violate in many cases, but even when we do so, we must continue to pretend that we are satisfying it. But that is a very idiosyncratic picture; and itâs not clear, in the end, how much is being saved of the standard strong-norm picture.
Maybe youâre still attracted to that view. If so, we have another, more empirical argument against it. Epistemic Posturing is a norm specifically tied to speech acts, while the picture we are considering now is about satisfying a norm by pretense more generally. But as we have seen, the infelicity of Moorean sentences is extremely local to the speech act in question. While it is unacceptable to assert âp but Iâm not certain that pâ, it is fine to assert p while, in a prior or subsequent speech act, acknowledging that you arenât certain of p. We saw this in the game-show case above, where it is perfectly fine to say you donât know p, and then in a subsequent speech act assert p. Compare also âThe war started in 1760. I donât know if thatâs right, but itâs my best guess!â which is completely fine.22 By putting the expression of uncertainty in a subsequent, separate speech act, the assertion is saved. But clearly there is no conversation-level pretense here that the speaker is certain that the war started in 1760: she says explicitly that she isnât!
Thus it looks like the ban on admitting uncertainty about p while asserting p is incredibly local to the speech act of assertion: outside of that speech act, there is not a general, conversation-level pretense that what was asserted is certain.
This is accounted for by our proposal, but not by the proposal under discussion. We could elaborate that proposal by saying that it is local to speech acts. But then that proposal collapses into ours.23
Epistemic Posturing is deeply puzzling. Why would a norm like this exist? We donât know, and clearly an explanation is needed: indeed, as it stands, Epistemic Posturing is nothing more than a compact description of the observations weâve drawn out. But if there is indeed a Posturing norm on orders, itâs relatively unsurprising that a similar norm would exist for assertions, even if more explanation of both is needed.
Before considering the range of Moorean infelicities, we assumed, with most philosophers, that the SAS was right. But as far as we can tell, the cases we explored above suggest it is not. Epistemic Posturing does a better job of explaining Moorean phenomena. With that said, let us emphasize that, as far as the broader goals of this paper go, weâre very open to other explanations of Moorean sentences. Our central point is the negative one: since the SAS does not work, Moorean phenomena do not provide good evidence for strong norms of assertion.
6 Conclusion
Assertion is weak. When we focus on the everyday-discourse patterns in (1) what we say, (2) how we get other people to say things, and (3) how we report what they say, we find that they are inconsistent with assertion being strong. Moreover, the best arguments for strong assertionâfrom âHow do you know?â and Moorean sentencesâturn out to be surprisingly unconvincing.
This is mostly a negative paper: our central goal has been to argue against a prevailing family of views about norms of assertion. But having said what we think assertion is not, weâd like to close by saying a bit about what we think assertion is.
First, to reprise a point from §3.1.2: while we are open to fine-grained taxonomies, we think that (what we have been calling) assertions are an interestingly unified class, since they are all, rather surprisingly, subject to an anti-Moorean norm. On top of that, we think assertions are also all governed by the norm: say the strongest thing you believe about the question under discussion. In concluding, weâll say a bit more about how to think about the norm.
That norm is superficially familiar enough. But we think belief is weak, so Entitlement Equality comes out true: both belief and assertion are weak. Moreover, we thinkthey are both weak in a very distinctive way. In particular, weâre sympathetic to a theory of weak belief developed in HolguĂn (2022). HolguĂn argues that what it is to believe p, relative to a given question, is for p to be entailed by your best guess about that question. He argues that this gives rise to a variety of interesting patterns concerning what you can and canât reasonably believe.
We think that picture is right. Moreover, we think a natural Jamesian (1897) idea from Levi 1967, which we develop further in Dorst and Mandelkern fc., helps explain these patterns in both guesses and beliefs. The basic idea is that in forming your best guess, you are implicitly maximizing a tradeoff: you want your guess to be accurate but also informative. The concern for accuracy provides reason to guess something youâre confident is true, since true guesses are better than false ones. But the concern for informativity provides reason to guess something that narrows down the space of alternatives, since more informative (true) guesses are better than less informative ones. The optimal way to balance this tradeoff varies with your level of epistemic risk aversion.
In the limiting case, when accuracy is all we care about, it makes sense to guess only what youâre absolutely certain of (âJohn will bring something for dinnerâ). But in normal contexts, it often makes sense to guess something more specific (âJohn will bring Indianâ), since the value of an informative guess outweighs the risk that it might be false.
Our proposal: whatâs true for belief and guessing is also true for assertion.24 While we canât make a detailed case for this here, we will briefly spell out some virtues of this proposal (we develop the idea more, with different arguments for its applicability to assertion, in Dorst and Mandelkern fc.).
First, it explains the connection between assertion and truth. Since true guesses/beliefs are better than false ones, likewise for assertions: both aim at truth (cf. Marsili 2018, 2021).
Second, it explains the connection between assertion and the question under discussion (Roberts 2012). More informative guesses/beliefs are better than less informative ones, and informativity, on our picture, is question-relative. Thus the same goes for assertions: both aim at informativity, relative to the question being consider.
Third, it explains why assertion is weak: assertion is weak because relatively improbable things can also be your best guess, provided they are sufficiently informative. In the right contextâfor example, prompted by âWho do you think will win the lottery?âââClaire will winâ is an acceptable assertion because, if true, itâs very informative.
But, finally, guessers have to figure out how to optimize the tradeoff between informativity and accuracy in a given situation. That flexibility helps explain how and why the norms of assertion may vary: in some, epistemically risk averse, contexts you can only say (think) what you are certain of; in other, epistemically permissive contexts, you can say (think) whatever youâre inclined toward, even if itâs relatively improbable. This variation is explained by changes in epistemic risk aversionâa free parameter that can be negotiated and adjusted by conversational participants.25
We think this flexibility helps explain why many have thought assertion is strong: theyâve focused on contexts in which accuracy is more heavily weighted than informativity. Nevertheless, we think itâs clear that many contexts are not like this. When you ask a grocery clerk where you can find the butternut squash, youâre not worried about them saying something thatâs not totally certainâyou just want a helpful pointer.
This variation explains why a lack of knowledge or certainty is sometimes treated as a good grounds for complaint, sometimes not. It also makes sense of why reactions like âAre you sure?â or âDo you know that?â are natural responses, whereas âDo you think that?â is much more aggressive: the former can be used to negotiate the level of evidence required for assertion, while the latter suggests that the speaker may have violated assertionâs fundamental norm.
More generally, we think this theory gives an intuitive overall picture of what assertion is, and why it is weak. Assertion is weak because we do not use assertions simply to transmit knowledge or certainties, but also to form and communicate pictures of the world that go beyond our certainties: we aim not only to avoid error, but also to acquire and share an informative picture of the world. For that reason, much of what we say involves coordinating on a picture that goes beyond what we are certain of. For limited agents like us, we canât afford to stick to our certainties; we often must take a stand that goes beyond them. Assertion is how we coordinate on that stand.
Acknowledgments
Weâre very grateful to reviewers at Sinn und Bedeutung and Philosophersâ Imprint, audiences at the New York Philosophy of Language Workshop and NYU Philosophy, and Bob Beddor, Matthew Benton, Sam Carter, Roger Clarke, Alexander Dinges, Cian Dorr, Diego Feinmann, John Hawthorne, Ben HolguĂn, Cameron Domenico Kirk-Giannini, Manfred Krifka, Harvey Lederman, Annina Loets, Neri Marsili, Dilip Ninan, Daniel Rothschild, Ginger Schultheis, Levi Spectre, Robert Stalnaker, Andreas Stokke, and Julia Zakkou for very helpful discussion.
Notes
- For examples, see Unger 1975; Williamson 2000, Ch. 11; Douven 2006; Lackey 2007, 2011, 2016; Stone 2007; Brown 2008, 2011; Levin 2008; Bach 2008; Adler 2009; Kvanvig 2009; Turri 2010a, b, 2011, 2016a, b; Benton 2011, 2012, 2016a, b; DeRose 2000; Maitra 2011; McKinnon 2012; McKinnon and Turri 2013; Kneer 2018, 2021; Benton and van Elswyk 2020; Willard-Kyle 2020. While we donât know of any explicit arguments that assertion is weak in all the senses we will spell out, this view is very much in the spirit of Stalnakerâs framework, in which assertions aim to update a common ground which can track weak attitudes of acceptance (Stalnaker 2002). Our view is slightly different: on our view, assertion does, as a rule, go by beliefâitâs just that belief is itself a weak notion. And our focus is on norms of assertion, rather than the related question of how assertions update the common ground (see §5.3 for discussion). The most important precedent for our view is Oppy 2007, which unfortunately only came to our attention as this paper was going to press, preventing us from giving it a full discussion. Short story: Oppy also uses prediction- and lottery-casesâas well as considerations about the ways weak norms can be supplementedâto suggest that the norm of assertion is belief, understood as being weaker than certainty (or knowledge). But he doesnât seem to think that belief (or assertion) is as weak as we doâfor instance, he does not defend (iv) or (v) below. âź
- See also Kahneman and Tversky 1982; Windschitl and Wells 1998; Dorst 2019; and HolguĂn 2022. âź
- Weâll move freely between âthinkâ and âbelieveâ, following the recent literature; weâll also assume the people in our examples are rational, and so match their credences and beliefs to their evidence. When we say credence, we mean rational credence, a.k.a. epistemic probability. âź
- See e.g., Williamson 2000; Stalnaker 2006; Buchak 2014, and Staffel 2016. âź
- Some are happy with (1) but resist (2). If youâre among them, then you still agree with use that belief can be quite weakâwe just disagree about how weak it can reasonably be. âź
- It certainly includes your evidence and rational credences, perhaps also the question under discussion (Roberts 2012; HolguĂn 2021), facts about normality (Smith 2016; Goodman and Salow 2018; Carter 2022), pragmatic stakes (Weatherson 2005; Ganson 2008), and epistemic risk aversion (Dorst and Mandelkern fc., and §6 below). âź
- Some are skeptical that thereâs a unified norm of assertion (Stone 2007; Levin 2008; Sosa 2009; McKinnon 2015), and others have suggested that there are various assertion-like speech acts with varying norms (Turri 2010a; Cappelen 2011; Pagin 2016; Zakkou 2021). We are inclined to disagreeâthere is at least one unifying feature of such speech acts, namely that Moorean utterances are ruled out across the board (see §3.1.2). Nevertheless, our negative arguments are mostly consistent with these positions. âź
- Some people agree with intuitions up to here, but think that (9b) is not acceptable. If you are one of them, then you still agree with most of our claims about the weakness of assertionâthat is, youâre on board with Theses (i)â(iv), but not (v); and, again, weâre happy to have taken you that far away from the orthodoxy. âź
- Here we deviate from authors who take the speech act of prediction to have its own (weaker) normative standards which differ from assertion (Benton 2012; Benton and Turri 2014; Cariani 2020; Ninan 2021a). Some may want to characterize all of our examples, including past-directed ones, as predictions, saving âassertionâ for something stronger; see §3.1.2 for discussion. âź
- Interestingly, in response to related questions like âWho does Mark think will win?â, a bare NP âJoeâ seems fine. Likewise, such bare-NP responses can be okay in Moorean contextsâfor example, itâs fine to respond to âWho do you think will win the race?â with âJoe, but Iâm not sure he willâ. These two contrasts suggest that ellipsis of the kind in question is indeed possible for bare NPs, but not for full clauses. âź
- âAssertâ is stilted, so weâll default to using âsayââbut we think the results are the same using either verb. âź
- A related observation that we think supports our argument is an intriguing contrast:
(35)
?John will probably bring Indian, but Iâm not saying that heâll bring Indian.
Itâs more probable than not that John will bring Indian, but Iâm not saying that heâll bring Indian.
- See Stone 2007; Kvanvig 2009; Turri 2010b; McKinnon 2012, and Kneer 2018 for related responses. âź
- âDo you think that?â improves with focus on âthatâ or âthink thatâ, whereas it doesnât seem to work at all with focus just on âthinkâ, suggesting that insofar as it can be used as a rejoinder, it is being used to query the content of the assertion rather than the attitude in question. âź
- Of course, as Diego Feinmann has pointed out to us, âHow do you know?â is a much more natural reply to an assertion than an explicit attitude claim. Compare:
(39)
[Liam:] John will bring Indian.
[Ezra:] How do you know?
(40)
[Liam:] I think John will bring Indian.
[Ezra:] ? How do you know?
- This observation goes back at least to Williams 1994, and has been discussed in the subsequent literature on prediction (e.g. Benton 2012; Cariani 2020). van Elswyk (2021) takes this point to be evidence for his view that declaratives like âThe war started in 1760â by default come with an unpronounced parenthetical âI knowâ (compare similar proposals in Chierchia 2006; Alonso-Ovalle and MenĂ©ndez-Benito 2010; Meyer 2013). However, as far as we can tell, the present data tell against such a view: in an exchange like the present one, it is completely unacceptable to say âOk, hm. I know that the war started in 1760â, since youâve just said you donât know. On van Elswykâs view, though, this is what (41) means. âź
- E.g. Williamson 2000; Stanley 2008; Sosa 2009; Clarke 2018; Dorst 2019; Moss 2019; Beddor 2020a, b. âź
- Itâs not that account has to merely say that itâs easy to raise standards for certainty; we agree about that. We even think that just mentioning skeptical possibilities might be enough to do so (DeRose 1992; Lewis 1996). But this isnât enough: the account weâre targeting must say that simply using âcertaintyâ invariably raises the standards. But thatâs wrong. As Cross 2010 points out, simply saying things like âYou might not have handsâ is not a good way to move to a skeptical context. Instead, you have to use the right sort of intensifier (âAre you absolutely sureâŠ?â), or raise a salient counter-possibility (âWhat if youâre a brain in a vat?â), etc. âź
- The closest proposal to this in the existing literature that we know of is in Condoravdi and Lauer 2011, which argues that an assertion of p is a public commitment to act as if you believe that p is true. Our proposal is similar to this, though with belief strengthened to certainty, and restricted to single speech acts. For other ideas in the neighborhood, compare Ninanâs (2021b) suggestion that to represent someone as believing p is to represent them as disposed to act as if they know that p, and Lauerâs (2012) suggestion that pragmatic slack is to be explained in terms of pretense norms. âź
- If in asserting âJohn will bring Indianâ you adopt a pretense of certainty in this claim, why canât you likewise say âJohn will bring Indian; Iâm certain of itâ? Presumably because (you know that) youâre not certain of it, and you shouldnât assert things you know are false. âź
- Thanks to Dilip Ninan and Daniel Rothschild for helpful discussion of this point. Yet another approach would be a âloose talkâ kind of knowledge norm (Moss 2019)âwe think this would be subject to the same worries. Generally speaking, while there are superficial similarities between weak assertion and loose talk (on which see Lasersohn 1999) they are very different phenomena (most obviously: in cases of loose talk, you are asserting something which you know to be false when interpreted literally, as when you say âJohn is six feet tallâ when in fact he is just shy of six feet; whereas in the cases we have focused on, you never say something you know to be false). In fact, cases of loose talk constitute, to our knowledge, the best kind of prima facie counterexample to the norm that you should only say what you think (though of course they may not be genuine counterexamples, if what is asserted is in fact the proposition that, say, John is roughly six feet tall). âź
- Thanks to John Hawthorne for this example. A tricky class of cases comes from hedges: cases like âThe warâIâm just guessing here, I donât knowâstarted in 1760â, which are fine (thanks again to John Hawthorne). We see two ways of dealing with this: (i) say that the asserted content here is âMy guess is that the war started in 1760â; (ii) distinguish two speech acts, the speech act of asserting that the war started in 1760, and the speech act of hedging it (cf. Krifka 2014; Benton and van Elswyk 2020). Both options would make the goodness of these cases consistent with Epistemic Posturing. âź
- You might be worried that our approach doesnât explain why you canât believe Moorean assertions. But thatâs misguidedâyou can believe them, since belief is weak! Since you can say âI think (p, but I donât know p)â, presumably you can also think p, but I donât know p. (Of course, you canât be certain of Moorean sentences, simply because âcertainâ is strong in some relevant sense.) âź
- Need assertion follow the same accuracy-informativity tradeoff as belief? Our core idea would be preserved if assertions instead always care at least as much about accuracy as guesses/beliefs do. But itâs natural to think the two will go precisely together. Admittedly, some high-stakes contexts might suggest that assertions must be more sensitive to accuracy than beliefs. When asked, âI really need to deposit a check; is the bank open?â, if youâre not sure, then its infelicitous to reply with âItâs openâ, but itâs fine to reply with âI think itâs openâ. However, this can be explained by the implicature story from §3.3.2: in such contexts, itâs important to report whether you know, and âI think itâs openâ conveys that you donât know (via implicature), whereas âItâs openâ leaves open that you do. Another question helpfully pressed by Cian Dorr is whether belief really matters at all: if two people have the same credences, could their assertions have normatively different statuses? As far as we can tell, the answer is yes. If you think Miriam wonât win the lottery, itâs fine to say she wonât. But if (having the same credence) you suspend judgment about whether sheâll win or not, it seems very odd to say she wonât. âź
- For other approaches to the flexibility of the norms of assertion, see for example Levin 2008; Sosa 2009; McKinnon 2015; Pagin 2016; Benton and van Elswyk 2020. âź
References
Adler, J. E., 2009. âAnother Argument for the Knowledge Normâ. Analysis, 69(3):407â411.
Alonso-Ovalle, Luis and MenĂ©ndez-Benito, Paula, 2010. âModal Indefinitesâ. Natural Language Semantics, 18:1â31.
Bach, Kent, 2008. âApplying Pragmatics to Epistemologyâ. Philosophical Issues, 18:68â88.
Beddor, Bob, 2020a. âCertainty in Actionâ. Philosophical Quarterly, 70(281):711â737.
Beddor, Bob, 2020b. âNew Work for Certaintyâ. Philosophers Imprint, 20(8):1â25.
Benton, M. A., 2011. âTwo More for the Knowledge Account of Assertionâ. Analysis, 71(4):684â687.
Benton, M. A., 2012. âAssertion, Knowledge and Predictionsâ. Analysis, 72(1):102â105.
Benton, Matthew A, 2016a. âExpert Opinion and Second-Hand Knowledgeâ. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92(2):492â508.
Benton, Matthew A., 2016b. âGricean Qualityâ. NoĂ»s, 50(4):689â703.
Benton, Matthew A. and Turri, John, 2014. âIffy Predictions and Proper Expectationsâ. Synthese, 191(8):1857â1866.
Benton, Matthew A and van Elswyk, Peter, 2020. âHedged Assertionâ. In Sanford Goldberg, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Assertion, 245â263. Oxford University Press.
Brown, Jessica, 2008. âThe Knowledge Norm for Assertionâ. Philosophical Issues, 18(1):89â103.
Brown, Jessica, 2011. âFallibilism and the Knowledge Norm for Assertion and Practical Reasoningâ. In Jessica Brown and Herman Cappelen, eds., Assertion: New Philosophical Essays, 153â174. Oxford University Press.
Buchak, Lara, 2014. âBelief, Credence, and Normsâ. Philosophical Studies, 169(2):285â311.
Cappelen, Herman, 2011. âAgainst Assertionâ. In Jessica Brown and Herman Cappelen, eds., Assertion: New Philosophical Essays, 21â48. Oxford University Press.
Cariani, Fabrizio, 2020. âOn Predictingâ. Ergo, 7(11):339â361.
Carter, Sam, 2022. âDegrees of Assertabilityâ. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 104(1):19â49.
Chierchia, Gennaro, 2006. âBroaden Your Views: Implicatures of Domain Widening and the âLogicalityâ of Languageâ. Linguistic Inquiry, 37:535â590.
Clarke, Roger, 2018. âAssertion, Belief, and Contextâ. Synthese, 195(11):4951â4977.
Condoravdi, Cleo and Lauer, Sven, 2011. âPerformative Verbs and Performative Actsâ. In Ingo Reich eds., Sinn und Bedeutung, volume 15, 149â164. Saarland University Press, SaarbrĂŒcken, Germany.
Cross, Troy, 2010. âSkeptical Successâ. Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 3:35â62.
DeRose, Keith, 1992. âContextualism and Knowledge Attributionsâ. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52(4):913â29.
DeRose, Keith, 1995. âSolving the Skeptical Problemâ. The Philosophical Review, 104(1):1â52.
DeRose, Keith, 2000. âNow you know it, now you donâtâ. The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, 5:91â106.
Dorst, Kevin, 2019. âLockeans Maximize Expected Accuracyâ. Mind, 128(509):175â211.
Dorst, Kevin and Mandelkern, Matthew, fc. âGood Guessesâ. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, To appear.
Douven, Igor, 2006. âAssertion, Knowledge and Rational Credibilityâ. Philosophical Review, 115(4):449â485.
van Elswyk, Peter, 2021. âRepresenting knowledgeâ. Philosophical Review, 130(1):97â143.
Ganson, Dorit, 2008. âEvidentialism and Pragmatic Constraints on Outright Beliefâ. Philosophical Studies, 139:441â458.
Goodman, Jeremy and Salow, Bernhard, 2018. âTaking a Chance on KKâ. Philosophical Studies, 175(1):183â196.
Hawthorne, John, Rothschild, Daniel, and Spectre, Levi, 2016. âBelief is weakâ. Philosophical Studies, 173(5):1393â1404.
HolguĂn, Ben, 2021. âKnowledge by Constraintâ. Philosophical Perspectives, 35(1):275â302.
HolguĂn, Ben, 2022. âThinking, Guessing, and Believingâ. Philosophersâ Imprint, 22(1):1â34.
James, William, 1897. The Will to Believe. Longmans, Green, and Co.
Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, 1982. âVariants of uncertaintyâ. Cognition, 11:143â157.
Katzir, Roni, 2007. âStructurally-Defined Alternativesâ. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(6):669â690.
Kneer, Markus, 2018. âThe Norm of Assertion: Empirical Dataâ. Cognition, 177:165â171.
Kneer, Markus, 2021. âNorms of Assertion in the United States, Germany, and Japanâ. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 118(37):1â3.
Krifka, Manfred, 2014. âEmbedding Illocutionary Actsâ. In T. Roeper and M. Speas, eds., Recursion: Complexity in Cognition, volume 43 of Studies in Theoretical Psycholinguistics, 59â87. Springer.
Kvanvig, Jonathan L, 2009. âAssertion, knowledge, and lotteriesâ. In Duncan Pritchard and Patrick Greenough, eds., Williamson on Knowledge, 140â160. Oxford University Press.
Kyburg, Henry E, 1964. âRecent Work in Inductive Logicâ. American Philosophical Quarterly, 1(4):249â287.
Lackey, Jennifer, 2007. âNorms of Assertionâ. NoĂ»s, 41(4):594â626.
Lackey, Jennifer, 2011. âAssertion and Isolated Second-Hand Knowledgeâ. In Jessica Brown and Herman Cappelen, eds., Assertion: New Philosophical Essays, 251â276. Oxford University Press.
Lackey, Jennifer, 2016. âAssertion and Expertiseâ. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92(2):509â517.
Lasersohn, Peter, 1999. âPragmatic Halosâ. Language, 75(3):522â551.
Lauer, Sven, 2012. âOn the Pragmatics of Pragmatic Slackâ. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, volume 16, 389â401.
Levi, Isaac, 1967. Gambling with Truth. The MIT Press.
Levin, Janet, 2008. âAssertion, Practical Reason, and Pragmatic Theories of Knowledgeâ. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(2):359â384.
Lewis, David, 1970. âGeneral Semanticsâ. Synthese, 22:18â67.
Lewis, David, 1996. âElusive Knowledgeâ. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4):549â567.
Maitra, Ishani, 2011. âAssertion, Norms, and Gamesâ. In Jessica Brown and Herman Cappelen, eds., Assertion: New Philosophical Essays, 277â296. Oxford University Press.
Makinson, D. C., 1965. âThe Paradox of the Prefaceâ. Analysis, 25:205â207.
Mandelkern, Matthew, 2021. âPractical Moore Sentencesâ. NoĂ»s, 55(1):39â61.
Marsili, Neri, 2018. âTruth and Assertion: Rules Versus Aimsâ. Analysis (United Kingdom), 78(4):638â648.
Marsili, Neri, 2021. âTruth: The Rule or the Aim of Assertion?â Episteme, 1â7.
McKinnon, Rachel, 2012. âHow Do You Know That 1How Do You Know?â Challenges a Speakerâs Knowledge?â Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 93(1):65â83.
McKinnon, Rachel, 2015. Norms of Assertion: Truth, Lies, and Warrant. Palgrave-Macmillan.
McKinnon, Rachel and Turri, John, 2013. âIrksome assertionsâ. Philosophical Studies, 166(1):123â128.
Meyer, Marie-Christine, 2013. Ignorance and Grammar. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Moss, Sarah, 2019. âFull belief and loose speechâ. Philosophical Review, 128(3):255â291.
Ninan, Dilip, 2021a. âAssertion, Evidence, and the Futureâ. Manuscript, Tufts University.
Ninan, Dilip, 2021b. âKnowing, Believing, and Acting as if You Knowâ. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, To appear.
Oppy, G., 2007. âNorms of Assertionâ. In D. Greimann and G. Siegwart, eds., Truth and Speech Act: Studies in the Philosophy of Language, 226â249. Routledge.
Pagin, Peter, 2016. âProblems With Norms of Assertionâ. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(1):178â207.
Percus, Orin, 2006. âAntipresuppositionsâ. In A. Ueyama, ed., Theoretical and Empirical Studies of Reference and Anaphora: Toward the establishment of generative grammar as an empirical science, 52â73. Japan Society for the Promotion of Science.
Roberts, Craige, 2012. âInformation Structure: Towards an Integrated Formal Theory of Pragmaticsâ. Semantics and Pragmatics, 5(6):1â69.
Silk, Alex, 2015. âWhat Normative Terms Mean and Why It Matters for Ethical Theoryâ. In M. Timmons, ed., Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, volume 5, 296â325. Oxford University Press.
Silk, Alex, 2022. âWeak and Strong Necessity Modalsâ. In B. Dunaway and D. Plunkett, eds., Meaning, Decision, and Norms: Themes from the Work of Allan Gibbard, 203â245. Maize Books: Michigan Publishing, University of Michigan.
Smith, Martin, 2016. Between Probability and Certainty: What Justifies Belief. Oxford University Press Uk.
Sosa, David, 2009. âDubious Assertionsâ. Philosophical Studies, 146(2):269â272.
Staffel, Julia, 2016. âBeliefs, Buses and Lotteries: Why Rational Belief Canât Be Stably High Credenceâ. Philosophical Studies, 173:1721â1734.
Stalnaker, Robert, 1984. Inquiry. Cambridge University Press.
Stalnaker, Robert, 2002. âCommon Groundâ. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25:701â721.
Stalnaker, Robert, 2006. âOn the Logics of Knowledge and Beliefâ. Philosophical Studies, 128(1):169â199.
Stanley, Jason, 2008. âKnowledge and Certaintyâ. Philosophical Issues, 18:33â55.
Stone, Jim, 2007. âContextualism and Warranted Assertionâ. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 88:92â113.
Turri, John, 2010a. âEpistemic Invariantism and Speech Act Contextualismâ. Philosophical Review, 119(1):77â95.
Turri, John, 2010b. âPrompting Challengesâ. Analysis, 70(3):456â462.
Turri, John, 2011. âThe Express Knowledge Account of Assertionâ. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(1):37â45.
Turri, John, 2016a. Knowledge and the Norm of Assertion: An Essay in Philosophical Science. Open Book Publishers.
Turri, John, 2016b. âThe Point of Assertion Is To Transmit Knowledgeâ. Analysis, 76(2):130â136.
Unger, Peter, 1975. Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism. Oxford University Press.
Weatherson, Brian, 2005. âCan We Do Without Pragmatic Encroachment?â Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1):417â443.
Willard-Kyle, Christopher, 2020. âBeing in a Position to Know is the Norm of Assertionâ. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 101(2):328â352.
Williams, John N., 1994. âMoorean Absurdity and the Intentional âStructureâ of Assertionâ. Analysis, 54(3):160â166.
Williamson, Timothy, 2000. Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford University Press.
Williamson, Timothy, fc. âKnowledge, Credence, and the Strength of Beliefâ. In Amy Flowerree and Baron Reed, eds., Expansive Epistemology: Norms, Action, and the Social World, volume To appear, To appear. Routledge.
Windschitl, P. D. and Wells, G. L., 1998. âThe Alternative-Outcomes Effectâ. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75(6):1411â1423.
Yalcin, Seth, 2010. âProbability Operatorsâ. Philosophy Compass, 5(11):916â937.
Zakkou, Julia, 2021. âOn Proper Presuppositionâ. Manuscript, Bielefeld University.